Economics and Ergodicity
- Get link
- X
- Other Apps
Economics posits
human behaviour and thus human actions on the premise of utility maximization. Therefore,
the next step obviously was in calculating the expected utility. The expected
utility theory posits the economic agent being rational will evaluate all
possible outcomes of his or her action and the probability of their occurrence before
determining their action. In other words, the probability of the expected
outcome will determine the trajectory of behaviour on the part of the economic
agent. If the agent feels the probability is skewed towards a positive payoff,
they will go ahead with the action else they are likely to adopt a risk averse attitude
and go with the contrary action. Yet in real life, experiments have indicated
something to the contrary. While mathematically the actions do point towards a
probable positive outcome, the agents however shirk from undertaking those
actions. These have been explained through models like prospect theory in behavioural
economics. While the conventional economics theory would posit these actions as
irrational and thus going against the grain of economics, behavioural economics
comes to the rescue in the analysis of how agents view differently the expected
the positive outcomes and the expected negative outcomes. The concepts of
framing and anchoring go in some ways trying to explain the puzzles of preference
reversals or ownership effects or failure of transitivity in practice.
Economics
apparently assumes ergodicity in decision making. Yet as Nicholas Nassem Taleb
has pointed out the process are rarely ergodic. In other words, history does
not have a bearing on the the current trajectory of the outcomes expected from
economic agent’s actions. As Taleb would point out, lessons on how the past
pandemics behaved would hardly give any insights on how the current Chinese
pandemic has been behaving. In absence of ergodicity, the evaluation of actions
have to be undertaken differently if the outcomes could result in prospective
ruin events. For instance the current pandemic resulted out of the Chinese
virus is one such ruin event which if happens frequently might destroy human
life. Yet, economists tend to dismiss these concerns stating ergodicity does
not factor in economic decision making.
Meanwhile, there
is an interesting article in Bloomberg quoting an UK theoretical physicist Ole
Peters that everything one has learnt about modern economic theory is wrong. The
article is available here.
The sacrilege in the current context happens to be that Ole Peters is not an
economist but a physicist. This perhaps is sufficient for economists to dismiss
him. Many journals have rejected his paper on grounds of the readers not being
interested in the same. Yet Ole Peters raises certain points which cannot be
dismissed. He might be a physicist with little training in economics, but his
criticism does merit certain discussion.
The article
posits that if Peters is proved right, it potentially upsets the entire fulcrum
around which the modern economic thought has revolved around. As Peters suggests,
modern economic thought centres on the presence of ergodicity which he claims
is not present in real life. This thesis is something that finds support from
Taleb who was one of the first to build his case for managing non-ergodic
processes. In Peters’ analysis, the economic thought has to find itself
reshaped having its impact on areas like risk management to income inequality
to pandemic management. He expresses a feeling that something is not right in
the way it should be. He argues the economic thoughts and concepts are based on
flawed reasoning and thus need to be viewed with scepticism. However, he does
concede in the article that his ideas have not found much traction among the
economics fraternity. While many economists might dismiss him, his paper on ‘The
Ergodicity Problem in Economics’ has attracted quite a bit of attention. In fact,
a virtual conference planned on his works too has attracted significant number
of registrations. In his view, expected utility is calculated as average of all
possible outcomes of a given event. Therefore, mathematically, while it might
convey some direction, the agents in real life behave differently when they
have to place their gambles. In other words, the action is different when one
does not have a skin in the game and when one does have a skin in the game. Yet
these arguments have found solutions and economics has addressed it in the
past. Yet, there does exist some merit in his argument on expected utility theory.
It is important to note that while expected utility theory assumes absence of
information asymmetry, there do exists costs of information processing and
cognition. The cognitive constraints do manifest in decision making something behavioural
theories have factored. What is warranted is a reconciliation of behavioural and
classical and neo-classical schools of thoughts into arriving at insights on
decision making. Yet as Peters thesis suggests, it is far from likely.
The methodology
employed by Peters without doubt is highly mathematical something expected
given his training. At the same time, a group of neuroscientists in Copenhagen
are experimenting in their labs on subjects testing their attitude towards risk
taking. The subjects did change their behaviour and thus actions willing to
take higher risk when circumstances changed. Interestingly, the experiments
seemed to validate the thought process and equations put forth by Peters. Yet,
despite the apparent success in experimental economics, his ideas still do not
have takers in mainstream economics. Apparently, it is because of his outsider
image and also the fact that economics with certain adaptations can explain the
anomalies that get highlighted by researchers like Peters. Economics has always
assumed the presence of constraints in decision making. The objective of
neo-classical school is to project utility maximization in presence of income
constraints and projecting profit maximization in presence of cost constraints.
Yet these constraints might not be the only one. When one factors in the other
constraints like cognitive thinking or others, the economic actions of the agents
under study could be explained. The gap between the experimental economists and
the mainstream utility theory proponents arises in the failure to take into the
additional constraints that exist. Behavioural economics gives us the framework
to handle these non-income or non-cost constraints. Interestingly however,
there has been a thriller made around the ideas of Peters. While the actions
posited by economists might differ in practice, the solution lies in working out
the range of constraints around which the utility maximisation arises rather
than throwing the baby out with the bathwater.
- Get link
- X
- Other Apps
Comments
Post a Comment