Decision Making as Output and Bounded Rationality

  The classical economics theories proceed on the assumption of rational agents. Rationality implies the economic agents undertake actions or exercise choices based on the cost-benefit analysis they undertake. The assumption further posits that there exists no information asymmetry and thus the agent is aware of all the costs and benefits associated with the choice he or she has exercised. The behavioral school contested the decision stating the decisions in practice are often irrational. Implied there is a continuous departure from rationality. Rationality in the views of the behavioral school is more an exception to the norm rather a rule. The past posts have discussed the limitations of this view by the behavioral school. Economics has often posited rationality in the context in which the choices are exercised rather than theoretical abstract view of rational action. Rational action in theory seems to be grounded in zero restraint situation yet in practice, there are numerous restra

Why Government Has to Provide Public Goods? No Private Army or Police or Justice System!

 

Economics literature recognizes the differential nature of goods. Each good is unique in itself. It must be pointed out that in economics, good is something than enhances economic welfare while bad is something that reduces economic welfare. For practical reasons, one can assume economic welfare to be equivalent to social welfare. Secondly, contrary to public perception about distinctions between goods and services, economics literature clusters both of them into goods (the singular of which is good). The past post “Examining the Nature of Good” went to certain depth in examining the nature and classification of goods. The current post would seek to build up on the same and strive to understand why certain goods are provided in the market whereas certain goods are offered only by the government. In theory, nothing prevents the private sector from offering every good, or in other words converting each good into either private or club good. Similarly, nothing prevents the government from offering all goods itself including the private goods without changing the nature of the good. In fact the latter was the staple of the communist regimes. At least to a substantial extent the state occupied what PM Nehru would term as commanding heights of the economy.

 

What is of importance is not per se whether the government or private sector offers the goods, but the conditions in which the government has to offer certain goods by itself. In other words, the private sector by its very intrinsic nature would not be in the market for these goods. One can cite the example of national security and thus the armed forces. Across the world, the armed forces are a monopoly of the government. It is not that private sector does not offer national security services. There are enough private armies which do exist across parts of the world. Yet the private armies are more of an extra-state, extra-territorial actors engaged in armed conflicts and rebellion. Private sector does supply numerous goods to the armed forces but the nature of these goods is rivalrous whereas the private sector is absent in the armed forces themselves. Similar is the instance of the justice system. The judiciary is the preserve of the state. There are of course local panchayats so as to speak that are empowered to offer justice but these are more exceptions. They are generally in the areas where tribes reside and the tribals have certain unique practices which need to be preserved. Furthermore, these panchayats or territorial councils etc. have state sanction to exercise judicial power. The non-state actors enforcing judicial laws happen in failed states and therein too they are virtually a monopoly.

 

Likewise, we find such instances in law and order too. It is either the state or state sanctioned monopoly that rules the roost so as to speak. This might pose a question to the absence of the private sector in these areas. Towards understanding this, one must resort to enquiring about the nature of goods. The goods are characterized in their identity through the principles of exclusion and rivalry. The goods are either rivalrous or non-rivalrous while second paradigm being excludability or otherwise of the good. Rivalrous is inherently an intrinsic characteristic whereas the excludability is something of an acquired characteristic. This is something that needs to be decoded.

 

The goods mentioned above as with few others are characterized by non-rivalrousness as also non-excludability. One cannot argue that the state will not defend those who do not pay the costs of purchasing the goods. In other words, there is a problem of free rider. Free riding theorem suggests, that the nature of these goods makes it possible that many might not pay the price yet avail the benefits of these goods. The state by nature cannot prevent the non-taxpayers for instance from access to law and order or justice.  The free riding theorem is something that prevents the private sector from offering these public goods. If the private sector were to offer these goods, those who do avails of the services or rather buy these goods cannot be excluded. In the inherent dynamics of the private sector working, the important part is the price. It is the interplay between demand and supply. The imbalances lead to the changes in prices. If it were to price national security for instance at some price, there must exist a mechanism that would ensure that those who do not buy the good are deprived of its access. The excludability characteristic is something that has to exist. For instance, cable television, internet, swimming pools, classroom teaching are instances which can be non rivalrous in their offer. Yet along with the non-rivalry there exists a possibility of excludability. If someone is not a member of the swimming club, he or she can be deprived of its services. Similarly the agent who owns a private lake or a pond can deprive people from accessing the same. Yet it cannot be done in the context of the public goods.

 

Air is something that cannot be excluded. In fact, air is per se a natural public good since there is no one who can even claim ownership of the same. The same might not hold good for pastures which are non rivalrous indicating a possibility of what is termed as tragedy of commons. Yet public goods like defence, law and order, justice are something that have to be provided. These are the goods that enable the functioning of the society in its splendor. Therefore, there is a need for service provider who is willing to factor in the free rider problem. The private sector will not be able to do the same. In its absence the government has to step in. The government has to ensure that the citizens are not deprived of these services as they continue to function in their economic and social space. Economic space is something critical as is social space, yet in the absence of the above services, one would return to the natural state of affairs, if one were to borrow the phrase from Hobbes. Thus we observe the public goods are offered only by the government and not by the private sector.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Decision Making as Output and Bounded Rationality

The Chicken-Egg Conundrum of Economics

A Note on Supply-Demand Dynamics