Decision Making as Output and Bounded Rationality

  The classical economics theories proceed on the assumption of rational agents. Rationality implies the economic agents undertake actions or exercise choices based on the cost-benefit analysis they undertake. The assumption further posits that there exists no information asymmetry and thus the agent is aware of all the costs and benefits associated with the choice he or she has exercised. The behavioral school contested the decision stating the decisions in practice are often irrational. Implied there is a continuous departure from rationality. Rationality in the views of the behavioral school is more an exception to the norm rather a rule. The past posts have discussed the limitations of this view by the behavioral school. Economics has often posited rationality in the context in which the choices are exercised rather than theoretical abstract view of rational action. Rational action in theory seems to be grounded in zero restraint situation yet in practice, there are numerous restra

Robert Aumann's Agreement Theorem: A Note

 

In 1976, publishing in the Annals of Statistics, Robert J Aumann made a contribution that perhaps is not just significant but provokes certain debate. He propounded what has to come be known as the Aumann agreement theorem. It is about agreeing to disagree or rather there would be no agreeing to disagree. To Aumann, two people let’s say 1 and 2 are said to ha have common knowledge of an event E if both know it, 1 knows that 2 knows about it and 2 knows 1 knows about it and 1 knows that 2 knows 1 knows about it and so on. Implied is the knowledge about the event is public with no secrecy. Carrying on, the theorem suggests, if two people have the same priors and their posteriors for an event A are common knowledge, then there posteriors are equal. If one were to decode the meaning, it implies given the absence of information asymmetry about an event, the two people in knowledge of the events would hold the same views even though their source of information would have differed in quantity and quality. Some examination of this assertion would be in order. The piece will just delve into the basics of the theorem rather than making a value judgment in terms of its applications or otherwise.

 

The first assumption is that the agents are rational and they have common knowledge. Rational agents are those who have clear preferences. As one is aware preferences are complete, clear and transitive. Given their preferences are unambiguous, they would base their decisions on the expected cost benefit analysis of the outcomes they have modeled. The outcomes might be uncertain, yet uncertainty leads to probability being attached to each of the outcomes that are possible or anticipated. They assign the expected values to each outcome possible and thus based on the optimal expected outcome of the value, they exercise their choice. Common knowledge is a framework in economics and decision sciences wherein a group of agents have the knowledge of an event. Furthermore, as stated above, not only they know that they know the event but also everyone knows everyone knows about the event. In such a circumstances, they can be described to have common priors. Prior in statistics is about the probability distribution that would express one’s beliefs about some uncertain quantity before some evidence is taken into account.

 

Since they have common knowledge about their posterior probabilities, the posteriors would be equal and thus no agreement is possible on disagreement. Posterior probability of any random event is the conditional probability assigned to the event after the context is factored into the decision making. Posterior is something ex-post information about the event once the background is examined at certain length. Aumann assumes that it does not matter how information was obtained. In other words, each of the agents might have gained the knowledge of the event through different bits of information, but as long as the rational agents had the common knowledge, it was immaterial about the means of information being available. The final outcome as Aumann would project was there would be agreement between the agents irrespective of the number of agents given the conditions assigned above.

 

Yet, there would arise questions about the inter-temporal matters- whether the time frame is relevant in the context of the agreements being arrived at. There would also be the context to be examined about the efficiency of the process in the mathematical landscape. There are however many issues that might arise including the presence of priors not being common. If the priors are not common, then there would exist a need to measure the distance of the priors being held by the agents.

 

The blog “Marginal Revolution’ does of course present a nuanced view on the applicability of Agreement Theorem. In the views of the blogger, it is the common sense morality that prevails while related to self, yet when it comes to political standing, there would be the differences that would stand out. In fact, in the context of the societal understanding, putting up an individual point however unpopular it might be would perhaps be in self-interest. Yet, in the context where decisions are self-related, it might be common sense to accept the agreement. It gives an example of a hotel offering room service which everyone knows and agrees. There is yet a choice of travelling to another restaurant but there is disagreement over its location. Even if one has a feel about its location, the cost benefit analysis would naturally tend to skew in favor of opting for the room service over which there is general consensus. In some ways, in this context, the self-interest actually would dictate sort of Prisoner’s Dilemma which would result into the agreement.

 

There is of course can be speculation on its application in the legal context. Let us say there are two people who are witness to an event. They both know that the other knows about the event. If the Aumann were to be true, then both the witnesses would have to present a similar conclusion to the judge. Would the witnesses differ is something that has to be pondered about. As the eyewitnesses differs in their interpretation of the events, it begs to be questioned about the proposition put forth by Aumann. In this context, it might be argued that witness credibility would be in question. There is of course the question of each trusting the other. Moreover, it would be open to the question of examining the veracity of both the stories. Leave alone agreement or disagreement, there would arise the need to verify the correctness of the narrative. In this context, there is a possibility that the theorem might find its limitations.

 

The proposition does offer quite a bit of interesting insights into the decision making under conditions of common knowledge. The common knowledge might not exist to perfection but certainly offers a starting point for analysis of consensual decision making. There are bound to be disagreements within the organization or the society. The final decision is often the product of contestations around differing points of view. The theorem suggests the possibility of consensus under certain conditions. The stage for final analysis would however be the relaxation of those conditions and subsequent examination of decision making under those relaxations.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Decision Making as Output and Bounded Rationality

The Economics Origins of BCG Matrix

People and the Third Wave of Chinese Virus